Lockesdonkey
Liberal Jihadist
I've noticed that there is a severe lack of threads about the humanities on this forum, especially all of the interesting stuff that has gone on in the last century. So, without further ado, I begin.
Overview
On account of my (ongoing) Western education, I will focus essentially exclusively on modern Western philosophy. Western philosophy can be broadly divided into two groups, dating back from the end of the Renaissance: British Empiricism and Continental Rationalism; for some reason, they are generally just termed Empirical and Continental philosophy, respectively.
The school of empiricism--which while predominant in the English-speaking world also has adherents on the Continent, most notably in Austria and Germany--is based in the theory that the only things that are known are those that are directly observed by the senses--either directly or through someone else's reports. In the modern age it has focused chiefly on science, and its application to other fields. Empirical philosophy is the basis of modern democracy and capitalism, but has evolved to a point of being essentially the analysis of language and the use of logic. This field of philosophy was very active up until the 1950s and 1960s, when there were essentially no more ideas to discover--there simply wasn't too much more to say about it. It's still very much alive, as its products, such as symbolic logic, are such useful tools for more than just philosophy--they form an excellent system to view everything from mathematics to computer science to politics.
The larger school, continental philosophy, is much more diverse and less "hard," focused on the "meaning of life"-type questions, as opposed to the cold objects of the empiricists. Unlike empiricism, it (originally at least) denies that the senses are the exclusive source of knowledge, and, at several points in history, often doubted that the senses were a reliable source of knowlege: how do we know we're not all plugged into the Matrix, or something like that? This school is constantly developing, even right now.
I'm not going to get into Objectivism (a vaguely empiricist philosophy) in this post.
Now that I've explained everything from Descartes and Locke to Russell and Foucault in two paragraphs, without naming names, I'll actually bother explaining.
First, twentieth-century philosophy actually begins in the middle of the nineteenth, with the ideas of Søren Kierkegaard and Friederich Nietzsche. While they had some influence in their time, their primary influence occured in the twentieth century, after their deaths.
Two Men with Unpronouncable Names
I'll start with Kierkegaard. Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard did most of his work in the 1840s and 1850s, before he died young (at the age of 42) in 1855.
It was in Kierkegaard's lifetime that the Industrial Revolution came into full swing on the Continent after the ravages of the Napoleonic Wars, which had ended when Kierkegaard was 2. Raised by his father to be a devout Christian, his father's deathbed wish was for young Søren to become a pastor, which he did. At university, he found himself more interested in philosophy than theology, but his philosophy was nevertheless profoundly influenced by Christianity and much of his later writing and later life focused on the role of Christianity and on criticizing the hollowness of modern "Christendom" (i.e. the institutions and practices, rather than the doctrines, of Chrisitians).
Kierkegaard's life, during the mad race of the Industrial Revolution, caused him to see not progress but regression--an emptiness and a hollowness which was papered over by the material gains of industry. He blamed this on several factors, and engaged in a long argument with Hegelians over several issues, but he chiefly criticized the use of the objective truth in ALL matters, arguing that subjectivity IS truth, that truth IS subjectivity. The key, acording to Kierkegaard, is that the most important thing is for a person to discover his Self, and his Self is all. And to know the Self, one had to know truth, and to know truth, one had to be subjective. By rejecting subjectivity in favor of objectivity in matters where objectivity is not desirable, the Industrial Revolution, Kierkegaard argued, forced people into living a lie.
This general line of reasoning is regarded as the first Existentialism, which is the key to much of twentieth-century Continental (read: French, and, to a lesser extent, German) philosophy.
Another segment of Existentialism, the Absurd, was touched upon by Kierkegaard's Fear and Trembling, in which the "knight of faith" is one who gives up all, trusting the in the Absurd belief that God will bring it back to him. The Absurd is important for several philosophers later.
The other Man with an Unpronouncable Name is Friederich Nietzsche, a German who was only eleven at the time of Kierkegaard's death. Nietzsche, presumably, is more familiar to you; at least some of you played SMAC, where The Will To Power was a technology, complete with Nietzsche blurb. While the Will to Power is a key concept, it is not his ONLY concept.
Nietzsche also saw the emptiness left by the Industrial Revolution, but he argued that it wasn't an acceptance of the objective that did this, but Christianity and its "slave morality" of pity. While I don't wish to get into specifics, Nietzsche fundamentally argued that those who have strong senses of self, are individuals rather than a part of the crowd, should determine morality--a "master" morality, and that the objective of humans is to have a sense of self. He extended on Kierkegaard in many ways (even if he didn't intend to) by criticizing the Christian institutions of the day for twisting the original doctrines of Christianity--which, for him, were the words of Jesus, one of the few who ever got close to the status of Übermensch ("over-man" or individual of great power).
With that, we move on.
In the Wake of the Great War
While several philosophers did pick up on Keirkegaard and Nietzsche (Bergson, Sorel, and Pareto spring to mind) before the First World War, it was only after it that philosophy began to truly change.
The Great War and events in that time period utterly shattered the conceptions of the Western world. Going into the war, the West was confident in its moral superiority, technological progress, and the certainty of science. It was certain that it was the best that the world could produce, that it had a moral obligation to "civilize" the world because it was infinately more civilized than anyone else.
Then came the war.
Four years of utterly inhumane and largely pointless warfare which saw an entire generation decimated and scarred for life. Thousands of men cut down in a single attack by machine-gun fire to gain a few meters' worth of barren land. Disease in the trenches. The gas, killing and blinding and maiming soldiers silently. The pointless destruction of economies to be put into the unstoppable meatgrinder of the front. The utter horrors inflicted by one person on another, the young lives--some of them, such as Henry Moseley, the bright young chemist who invented the modern Periodic table--snuffed out too soon, in the name of what were supposed to be civilized governments--it was all too much. Common people began to realize what Kierkegaard and Nietzsche had seen so long ago: Life in the modern world is empty, pointless, hollow. There is no meaning anymore.
People started looking for answers. Trying to remain sane, they looked to their old consolers--philosophy and science.
Science had no answers for them: just as the war began, physics, queen of the sciences, always so precise, so certain, underwent a revolution. Einstein published his General Theory of Relativity in 1915; Max Planck's concepts of quantum theory began to be accepted as De Broglie came out with his equation proving the wave-particle duality, Schrodinger came out with his wave equation, and Heisenberg's uncertainty principle was published. Science now indicated that the physical world was as uncertain as the one of their lives. That was no comfort.
Neither did philosophy have any answers; empiricists' reaction was to decide that philosophy's only business was the clarification of thought, ergo, the analysis of language; other philosophers said, "Nice. Let's analyze this..." which was no comfort, either. Hence we see the booze flow in New York and Paris and everywhere else.
First, we address the empiricists. The empiricist reaction to the postwar world--the Age of Anxiety--is to declare the old questions about the meaning of life, the existance of God, and basically all of the other major philosophical questions of history meaningless. Ludwig Wittgenstein and his Vienna Circle declared that the only concepts worth thinking about philosophically were those (and forgive me for generalizing) that have verifiable (or falsifiable) truth values. Everything else is just personal opinion. This won him many supporters in stolidly empiricist Britain, where he eventually moved on the invitation of Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore, among others. Russell and Alfred North Whitehead codified the modern system of analytic, logical philosophy with their massive Principia Mathematica, which provides an unparalleled system for the analysis of language. At this point, discussion in the empirical field becomes largely pointless.
On the other side of the Channel, however, philosophy was humming along quite nicely--and increasingly bizzarely. German Martin Heidegger attempted to totally alter the framework of philosophy by shifting the focus from things that are to the meaning of what it is to be in the first place--in the terminology, ontology. Heidegger expressed concern about many things, and wrote extensively. He is chiefly important in this introduction, however, because a statement he made being misinterpreted by Sartre, and because of his influence on Derrida's Deconstruction, a philosophy in vogue since the late 1960s.
Jean-Paul Sartre is one of the last modern philosophers who largely make sense to somebody who reads a few articles about him. A Frenchman profoundly disturbed by the Great War, he developed Kierkegaard's existentialism, with elements of Nietzsche and the assertion that all life is absurd (corrupted from Heidegger's statement that all life has the potential to become absurd) to form modern existentialism, which remained popular (among philosophers, and to a lesser extent the public) through the 1960s. Essentially, Sartre's existentialism argues that there is a meaning of life: that which the individual assigns to it. There is no "great plan" to which anyone can adhere. Every moment is a struggle to maintain that meaning, a struggle against suicide--a theme carried on by Sartre's pupil, Albert Camus.
Camus delves deeper into the idea of suicide and through it, the Absurd--the fundamental contradictions and paradoxes that define life. Camus inspired a whole generation of Absurdist novelists, particularly (and this is bizzare) in the United States: Joseph Heller's Catch-22, as well as virtually all of Thomas Pynchon's novels, deal with the concept of the Absurd, as inspired by Camus. This synthesis of philosophy and literature forshadow a radical development to come.
Existentialism eventually faded away as several new concepts came to light. France, long the center of philosophy, became dominated by structuralism--too complicated to explain--in the 1960s, which quickly gave rise to post-structuralism and deconstruction: all part of postmodernism.
Postmodernism is a very large umbrella term for a group of ideas that hold several things to be true. Two keys:
1. That there is no social, religious or cultural truth. This differs somewhat from Wittgenstein's perspective in that a. logical positivists (as Wittgenstein's group is called) don't care whether or not there is a social, cultural, or religious truth, and that b. whereas logical positivists don't deal with social, religious, or cultural matters, postmodernists do.
2. That philosophy and literature are interconnected. This is particularly true of Derrida.
I will now go over some of the more important philosophers since the 1960s:
Michel Foucault was a key player in the recent philosophical world; an emphatic member of the social movements that swept the West in the 1960s, he found ways to meld them into philosophy. His monumental History of Sexuality introduced the concept that the idea of sexuality was invented to preserve a particular social order, among other things, and combined with the feminist concepts developed by Sartre's longtime partner Simone de Beauvoir, developed into the modern study of "Queer Theory."
Foucault also developed the concept of biopower: power by control of life. Essentially, it is the argument that in contrast to the old monarchies, where the state obtained its power by killing those who disobeyed, the modern state casts its job as protecting the lives of those who obey through military force and institutionalization of all kinds, with an assortment of ramifications, such as the Holocaust, nuclear weapons, and the banning of water on airplanes...
Jacques Derrida developed deconstruction. It's hard to explain. Moving on...
Jacques Lacan wasn't a philosopher so much as a psychologist. It's hard to explain him; I haven't done much research. Sorry. The most important thing I know about him is that he influenced Slavoj Zizek, who in addition to finding deep truth in Jaws and E.T., ran for the Presidency of Slovenia and lost, only to find himself living now with the party he ran for at the helm.
I'm currently in the middle of studying Gilles Deleuze. Suffice it to say that Foucault said only half-jokingly that people would call the 20th century the Age of Deleuze.
And finally, there is Edward Said. This Palestinian, exiled in the United States, actually began in literature; he held a major professorship at Columbia in comparative literature. However, modern critical theory (i.e. postmodernism) allows for easy shifting between the two, and Said's real passion was his homeland. Drawing heavily on feminist analysis, he analyzed the systematic oppression and "otherization" (feminist term) of the colonized peoples. I primarily mention him because I've read more of him and understand him better than any other; but change "colonized peoples" to "women" or "non-heterosexuals" and you have the fundamental concepts of postmodern feminism and queer theory, respectively.
And now I'm exhausted. Thank you.
Overview
On account of my (ongoing) Western education, I will focus essentially exclusively on modern Western philosophy. Western philosophy can be broadly divided into two groups, dating back from the end of the Renaissance: British Empiricism and Continental Rationalism; for some reason, they are generally just termed Empirical and Continental philosophy, respectively.
The school of empiricism--which while predominant in the English-speaking world also has adherents on the Continent, most notably in Austria and Germany--is based in the theory that the only things that are known are those that are directly observed by the senses--either directly or through someone else's reports. In the modern age it has focused chiefly on science, and its application to other fields. Empirical philosophy is the basis of modern democracy and capitalism, but has evolved to a point of being essentially the analysis of language and the use of logic. This field of philosophy was very active up until the 1950s and 1960s, when there were essentially no more ideas to discover--there simply wasn't too much more to say about it. It's still very much alive, as its products, such as symbolic logic, are such useful tools for more than just philosophy--they form an excellent system to view everything from mathematics to computer science to politics.
The larger school, continental philosophy, is much more diverse and less "hard," focused on the "meaning of life"-type questions, as opposed to the cold objects of the empiricists. Unlike empiricism, it (originally at least) denies that the senses are the exclusive source of knowledge, and, at several points in history, often doubted that the senses were a reliable source of knowlege: how do we know we're not all plugged into the Matrix, or something like that? This school is constantly developing, even right now.
I'm not going to get into Objectivism (a vaguely empiricist philosophy) in this post.
Now that I've explained everything from Descartes and Locke to Russell and Foucault in two paragraphs, without naming names, I'll actually bother explaining.
First, twentieth-century philosophy actually begins in the middle of the nineteenth, with the ideas of Søren Kierkegaard and Friederich Nietzsche. While they had some influence in their time, their primary influence occured in the twentieth century, after their deaths.
Two Men with Unpronouncable Names
I'll start with Kierkegaard. Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard did most of his work in the 1840s and 1850s, before he died young (at the age of 42) in 1855.
It was in Kierkegaard's lifetime that the Industrial Revolution came into full swing on the Continent after the ravages of the Napoleonic Wars, which had ended when Kierkegaard was 2. Raised by his father to be a devout Christian, his father's deathbed wish was for young Søren to become a pastor, which he did. At university, he found himself more interested in philosophy than theology, but his philosophy was nevertheless profoundly influenced by Christianity and much of his later writing and later life focused on the role of Christianity and on criticizing the hollowness of modern "Christendom" (i.e. the institutions and practices, rather than the doctrines, of Chrisitians).
Kierkegaard's life, during the mad race of the Industrial Revolution, caused him to see not progress but regression--an emptiness and a hollowness which was papered over by the material gains of industry. He blamed this on several factors, and engaged in a long argument with Hegelians over several issues, but he chiefly criticized the use of the objective truth in ALL matters, arguing that subjectivity IS truth, that truth IS subjectivity. The key, acording to Kierkegaard, is that the most important thing is for a person to discover his Self, and his Self is all. And to know the Self, one had to know truth, and to know truth, one had to be subjective. By rejecting subjectivity in favor of objectivity in matters where objectivity is not desirable, the Industrial Revolution, Kierkegaard argued, forced people into living a lie.
This general line of reasoning is regarded as the first Existentialism, which is the key to much of twentieth-century Continental (read: French, and, to a lesser extent, German) philosophy.
Another segment of Existentialism, the Absurd, was touched upon by Kierkegaard's Fear and Trembling, in which the "knight of faith" is one who gives up all, trusting the in the Absurd belief that God will bring it back to him. The Absurd is important for several philosophers later.
The other Man with an Unpronouncable Name is Friederich Nietzsche, a German who was only eleven at the time of Kierkegaard's death. Nietzsche, presumably, is more familiar to you; at least some of you played SMAC, where The Will To Power was a technology, complete with Nietzsche blurb. While the Will to Power is a key concept, it is not his ONLY concept.
Nietzsche also saw the emptiness left by the Industrial Revolution, but he argued that it wasn't an acceptance of the objective that did this, but Christianity and its "slave morality" of pity. While I don't wish to get into specifics, Nietzsche fundamentally argued that those who have strong senses of self, are individuals rather than a part of the crowd, should determine morality--a "master" morality, and that the objective of humans is to have a sense of self. He extended on Kierkegaard in many ways (even if he didn't intend to) by criticizing the Christian institutions of the day for twisting the original doctrines of Christianity--which, for him, were the words of Jesus, one of the few who ever got close to the status of Übermensch ("over-man" or individual of great power).
With that, we move on.
In the Wake of the Great War
While several philosophers did pick up on Keirkegaard and Nietzsche (Bergson, Sorel, and Pareto spring to mind) before the First World War, it was only after it that philosophy began to truly change.
The Great War and events in that time period utterly shattered the conceptions of the Western world. Going into the war, the West was confident in its moral superiority, technological progress, and the certainty of science. It was certain that it was the best that the world could produce, that it had a moral obligation to "civilize" the world because it was infinately more civilized than anyone else.
Then came the war.
Four years of utterly inhumane and largely pointless warfare which saw an entire generation decimated and scarred for life. Thousands of men cut down in a single attack by machine-gun fire to gain a few meters' worth of barren land. Disease in the trenches. The gas, killing and blinding and maiming soldiers silently. The pointless destruction of economies to be put into the unstoppable meatgrinder of the front. The utter horrors inflicted by one person on another, the young lives--some of them, such as Henry Moseley, the bright young chemist who invented the modern Periodic table--snuffed out too soon, in the name of what were supposed to be civilized governments--it was all too much. Common people began to realize what Kierkegaard and Nietzsche had seen so long ago: Life in the modern world is empty, pointless, hollow. There is no meaning anymore.
People started looking for answers. Trying to remain sane, they looked to their old consolers--philosophy and science.
Science had no answers for them: just as the war began, physics, queen of the sciences, always so precise, so certain, underwent a revolution. Einstein published his General Theory of Relativity in 1915; Max Planck's concepts of quantum theory began to be accepted as De Broglie came out with his equation proving the wave-particle duality, Schrodinger came out with his wave equation, and Heisenberg's uncertainty principle was published. Science now indicated that the physical world was as uncertain as the one of their lives. That was no comfort.
Neither did philosophy have any answers; empiricists' reaction was to decide that philosophy's only business was the clarification of thought, ergo, the analysis of language; other philosophers said, "Nice. Let's analyze this..." which was no comfort, either. Hence we see the booze flow in New York and Paris and everywhere else.
First, we address the empiricists. The empiricist reaction to the postwar world--the Age of Anxiety--is to declare the old questions about the meaning of life, the existance of God, and basically all of the other major philosophical questions of history meaningless. Ludwig Wittgenstein and his Vienna Circle declared that the only concepts worth thinking about philosophically were those (and forgive me for generalizing) that have verifiable (or falsifiable) truth values. Everything else is just personal opinion. This won him many supporters in stolidly empiricist Britain, where he eventually moved on the invitation of Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore, among others. Russell and Alfred North Whitehead codified the modern system of analytic, logical philosophy with their massive Principia Mathematica, which provides an unparalleled system for the analysis of language. At this point, discussion in the empirical field becomes largely pointless.
On the other side of the Channel, however, philosophy was humming along quite nicely--and increasingly bizzarely. German Martin Heidegger attempted to totally alter the framework of philosophy by shifting the focus from things that are to the meaning of what it is to be in the first place--in the terminology, ontology. Heidegger expressed concern about many things, and wrote extensively. He is chiefly important in this introduction, however, because a statement he made being misinterpreted by Sartre, and because of his influence on Derrida's Deconstruction, a philosophy in vogue since the late 1960s.
Jean-Paul Sartre is one of the last modern philosophers who largely make sense to somebody who reads a few articles about him. A Frenchman profoundly disturbed by the Great War, he developed Kierkegaard's existentialism, with elements of Nietzsche and the assertion that all life is absurd (corrupted from Heidegger's statement that all life has the potential to become absurd) to form modern existentialism, which remained popular (among philosophers, and to a lesser extent the public) through the 1960s. Essentially, Sartre's existentialism argues that there is a meaning of life: that which the individual assigns to it. There is no "great plan" to which anyone can adhere. Every moment is a struggle to maintain that meaning, a struggle against suicide--a theme carried on by Sartre's pupil, Albert Camus.
Camus delves deeper into the idea of suicide and through it, the Absurd--the fundamental contradictions and paradoxes that define life. Camus inspired a whole generation of Absurdist novelists, particularly (and this is bizzare) in the United States: Joseph Heller's Catch-22, as well as virtually all of Thomas Pynchon's novels, deal with the concept of the Absurd, as inspired by Camus. This synthesis of philosophy and literature forshadow a radical development to come.
Existentialism eventually faded away as several new concepts came to light. France, long the center of philosophy, became dominated by structuralism--too complicated to explain--in the 1960s, which quickly gave rise to post-structuralism and deconstruction: all part of postmodernism.
Postmodernism is a very large umbrella term for a group of ideas that hold several things to be true. Two keys:
1. That there is no social, religious or cultural truth. This differs somewhat from Wittgenstein's perspective in that a. logical positivists (as Wittgenstein's group is called) don't care whether or not there is a social, cultural, or religious truth, and that b. whereas logical positivists don't deal with social, religious, or cultural matters, postmodernists do.
2. That philosophy and literature are interconnected. This is particularly true of Derrida.
I will now go over some of the more important philosophers since the 1960s:
Michel Foucault was a key player in the recent philosophical world; an emphatic member of the social movements that swept the West in the 1960s, he found ways to meld them into philosophy. His monumental History of Sexuality introduced the concept that the idea of sexuality was invented to preserve a particular social order, among other things, and combined with the feminist concepts developed by Sartre's longtime partner Simone de Beauvoir, developed into the modern study of "Queer Theory."
Foucault also developed the concept of biopower: power by control of life. Essentially, it is the argument that in contrast to the old monarchies, where the state obtained its power by killing those who disobeyed, the modern state casts its job as protecting the lives of those who obey through military force and institutionalization of all kinds, with an assortment of ramifications, such as the Holocaust, nuclear weapons, and the banning of water on airplanes...
Jacques Derrida developed deconstruction. It's hard to explain. Moving on...
Jacques Lacan wasn't a philosopher so much as a psychologist. It's hard to explain him; I haven't done much research. Sorry. The most important thing I know about him is that he influenced Slavoj Zizek, who in addition to finding deep truth in Jaws and E.T., ran for the Presidency of Slovenia and lost, only to find himself living now with the party he ran for at the helm.
I'm currently in the middle of studying Gilles Deleuze. Suffice it to say that Foucault said only half-jokingly that people would call the 20th century the Age of Deleuze.
And finally, there is Edward Said. This Palestinian, exiled in the United States, actually began in literature; he held a major professorship at Columbia in comparative literature. However, modern critical theory (i.e. postmodernism) allows for easy shifting between the two, and Said's real passion was his homeland. Drawing heavily on feminist analysis, he analyzed the systematic oppression and "otherization" (feminist term) of the colonized peoples. I primarily mention him because I've read more of him and understand him better than any other; but change "colonized peoples" to "women" or "non-heterosexuals" and you have the fundamental concepts of postmodern feminism and queer theory, respectively.
And now I'm exhausted. Thank you.