insurgent
Exhausted
Everywhere we look, we seem to encounter choices and decisions waiting to be made. Corporations and individuals incessantly try to influence our decisions. They want something from us. We want something from our choices. But we never know what we will get. That is the fundamental problem.
Even though we may feel overwhelmed by the apparent abundance of choices in this modern consumer society, we should not delude ourselves into thinking that we are facing an insuperable challenge. We can go to the supermarket and choose between ten different kinds of yoghurt, five types of carrots, seventeen brands of coffee etc. The consumer decisions we face are many. The greater and perhaps more important decisions of life, love, and survival are still here for us to make. But our ancestors also had to choose. Perhaps they chose at a different level. Perhaps more of their decisions were a simple matter of life or death. But the essence of choosing has always been the same thing.
When we face a choice, tough or easy, simple or complicated, important or insignificant, we have to make a decision. This decision is based on considerations concerning the nature and consequences of what we do. We might choose between taking hiring a cab or waiting for a bus on a late evening. This relatively inconsequential decision will have to be based on considerations of price, time, and perhaps the expediency of the moment. In a different situation, we may choose whether or not to avenge the death of a close relative. We might feel like killing the person responsible, but the very nature of this act might keep us from doing it even though this is not the result of seriously contemplated consequences. The first decision was based on expectations of the result. After making clear to ourselves, which consequences we expect our actions or lack thereof to bring, we will choose based on what we want. This is based on our preferences, desires, dreams, attitude to life etc. In the second example, the decision is more of a matter of principle. Most of us would not even consider the consequences of murdering somebody, simply because we find it ethically objectionable.
The point of the above explanation is to say that each decision is based on the intentions of the individual. Each person has his own principles and desires. These constitute his free will based on his own individual and subjective ethics. This is crucial as it means that the right choice in any particular decision is different from one individual to the next. Nobody can attain complete understanding and knowledge of the wishes of everybody, and so each individual must per definition be the best arbiter of his own life. This, one might say, is the X-factoror the unknown variablewhich means that the criteria of decision-making are fundamentally different from person to person and situation to situation. We cannot possibly fully understand the decisions of other individuals. This is the most fundamental argument for leaving free choice to the individual.
This is the primary reason that no central authority should be entrusted with powers to restrict the free choice of the individual. Since everybody chooses based on his own preferences, the individual will choose what is best for him. So, consequently, restricting free choice by limiting the individuals options and possibilities of action cannot possibly improve the situation of the individual. If the best option is taken away, the individual will have to resort to a less desirable choice. If the option is not the best one for the individual, the situation will not be improved, as the individual would not have chosen it anyway. Instead there is just a loss of freedom. This line of argument is often heard in the context of prostitution. Advocates of a ban against prostitution often make the point that it would improve the conditions of women if prostitution were to be made illegal. But if some women choose to prostitute themselves, they must evidently find this better than the alternatives.
The process of removing responsibility from the individual and entrusting it to authorities might also mean that individuals stop paying as much attention to the consequences of their decisions: I wont bother to look into this situation. Thats what the governments for. If you take away freedom from the individual, he will have less reason to take any responsibility, and he will tend to blindly trust whoever handles his affairs.
Therefore, the most common argument against free choice also contains a logical fallacy. The point of view is basically that the individual has neither the capacity nor the resources to gain enough information to make a qualified decision. Therefore, leaving choices to experts may be reasonable. Doing this, however, would mean a transfer of responsibility from the individual to the expert authority. The individual would pay less intention and expect somebody else to handle his problems and thus make him even less capable of making his own decisions. Thus more responsibility would have to be transferred to the authorities, simply because the individual would expect someone else to handle his problems for him. In the end, central planning of many more aspects of human life would be the result. Combined with the primary argument against such central authoritiesthat they cannot possibly know the preferences of each individual and thus what is right for himit is clear that such an outcome would be undesirable.
Having established this, it needs to be said that the most serious problem of making decisions is the fact that you do not know the consequences of your actions or your inaction at the point when you make the decision. Just like a central authority, the individual can only try to foretell the consequences and anticipate a certain outcome. Information is needed to make the situation clearer, and so the individual will need to look into his choice. Doing this can seem tough and even impossible, when we are confronted with so many and so different choices. But since it is our decision to make, we seek this information, and suppliers of this information arise. The press constantly bombards us with consumer information and other types of information spread easily in our modern society. Though these sources of information may at first seem to only complicate the situation even further, they are extremely useful. They do not suddenly make it possible for the individual to know all about the future or even the present. They present us with another choice: what we want to know more about and therefore what we find it important to make more qualified decisions about.
The point of all this is that life is made up of choices. As time passes, we make conscious and unconscious decisions, and the decisions that we make constitute our lives. Though we may not always like the possibilities or outcomes, we should treasure our capacity to make choices. In order to make the right decisions and shape our lives, as we want to, we will need to be aware of the choices we have to make. We need to be conscious about our decisions for us to direct their outcome at some desirable objective. That is the only way for us to truly control our own lives.
Even though we may feel overwhelmed by the apparent abundance of choices in this modern consumer society, we should not delude ourselves into thinking that we are facing an insuperable challenge. We can go to the supermarket and choose between ten different kinds of yoghurt, five types of carrots, seventeen brands of coffee etc. The consumer decisions we face are many. The greater and perhaps more important decisions of life, love, and survival are still here for us to make. But our ancestors also had to choose. Perhaps they chose at a different level. Perhaps more of their decisions were a simple matter of life or death. But the essence of choosing has always been the same thing.
When we face a choice, tough or easy, simple or complicated, important or insignificant, we have to make a decision. This decision is based on considerations concerning the nature and consequences of what we do. We might choose between taking hiring a cab or waiting for a bus on a late evening. This relatively inconsequential decision will have to be based on considerations of price, time, and perhaps the expediency of the moment. In a different situation, we may choose whether or not to avenge the death of a close relative. We might feel like killing the person responsible, but the very nature of this act might keep us from doing it even though this is not the result of seriously contemplated consequences. The first decision was based on expectations of the result. After making clear to ourselves, which consequences we expect our actions or lack thereof to bring, we will choose based on what we want. This is based on our preferences, desires, dreams, attitude to life etc. In the second example, the decision is more of a matter of principle. Most of us would not even consider the consequences of murdering somebody, simply because we find it ethically objectionable.
The point of the above explanation is to say that each decision is based on the intentions of the individual. Each person has his own principles and desires. These constitute his free will based on his own individual and subjective ethics. This is crucial as it means that the right choice in any particular decision is different from one individual to the next. Nobody can attain complete understanding and knowledge of the wishes of everybody, and so each individual must per definition be the best arbiter of his own life. This, one might say, is the X-factoror the unknown variablewhich means that the criteria of decision-making are fundamentally different from person to person and situation to situation. We cannot possibly fully understand the decisions of other individuals. This is the most fundamental argument for leaving free choice to the individual.
This is the primary reason that no central authority should be entrusted with powers to restrict the free choice of the individual. Since everybody chooses based on his own preferences, the individual will choose what is best for him. So, consequently, restricting free choice by limiting the individuals options and possibilities of action cannot possibly improve the situation of the individual. If the best option is taken away, the individual will have to resort to a less desirable choice. If the option is not the best one for the individual, the situation will not be improved, as the individual would not have chosen it anyway. Instead there is just a loss of freedom. This line of argument is often heard in the context of prostitution. Advocates of a ban against prostitution often make the point that it would improve the conditions of women if prostitution were to be made illegal. But if some women choose to prostitute themselves, they must evidently find this better than the alternatives.
The process of removing responsibility from the individual and entrusting it to authorities might also mean that individuals stop paying as much attention to the consequences of their decisions: I wont bother to look into this situation. Thats what the governments for. If you take away freedom from the individual, he will have less reason to take any responsibility, and he will tend to blindly trust whoever handles his affairs.
Therefore, the most common argument against free choice also contains a logical fallacy. The point of view is basically that the individual has neither the capacity nor the resources to gain enough information to make a qualified decision. Therefore, leaving choices to experts may be reasonable. Doing this, however, would mean a transfer of responsibility from the individual to the expert authority. The individual would pay less intention and expect somebody else to handle his problems and thus make him even less capable of making his own decisions. Thus more responsibility would have to be transferred to the authorities, simply because the individual would expect someone else to handle his problems for him. In the end, central planning of many more aspects of human life would be the result. Combined with the primary argument against such central authoritiesthat they cannot possibly know the preferences of each individual and thus what is right for himit is clear that such an outcome would be undesirable.
Having established this, it needs to be said that the most serious problem of making decisions is the fact that you do not know the consequences of your actions or your inaction at the point when you make the decision. Just like a central authority, the individual can only try to foretell the consequences and anticipate a certain outcome. Information is needed to make the situation clearer, and so the individual will need to look into his choice. Doing this can seem tough and even impossible, when we are confronted with so many and so different choices. But since it is our decision to make, we seek this information, and suppliers of this information arise. The press constantly bombards us with consumer information and other types of information spread easily in our modern society. Though these sources of information may at first seem to only complicate the situation even further, they are extremely useful. They do not suddenly make it possible for the individual to know all about the future or even the present. They present us with another choice: what we want to know more about and therefore what we find it important to make more qualified decisions about.
The point of all this is that life is made up of choices. As time passes, we make conscious and unconscious decisions, and the decisions that we make constitute our lives. Though we may not always like the possibilities or outcomes, we should treasure our capacity to make choices. In order to make the right decisions and shape our lives, as we want to, we will need to be aware of the choices we have to make. We need to be conscious about our decisions for us to direct their outcome at some desirable objective. That is the only way for us to truly control our own lives.