Interesting. Can people naturally specialize at what they're good at, though, without being turned into two-bit automatons?
Suppose I'm making a computer game for sale: I'm not that good at graphics design but I'm pretty good at programming, so I hire someone else to do the graphics for me whose work I appreciate because it's better than mine. I can then sell the game (at the reasonable cost of labor) to someone who doesn't have the expertise or the creative energy to make his own entertainment. I compensate my hiree with 50% of the profits since he did half the work, and neither of us become automatons since we both derive great enjoyment from our jobs.
Can we be free of alienation and operate on the market at the same time? Or was the scenario I described too idealistic? Or am I missing something about how capital operates?
I don't think so, no. The condition of alienation is a product of what Marx calls the ontological inversion, better known as "commodity fetishism, the process by which the commodity-form is experienced (and it
is a subjectively accurate experience, not just "false conciousness") as something ontologically prior to its exchange on the market, and to which human social activity, i.e. capitalism is only a response, rather than the commodity-form being something which actually emerges out of human activity. (This is why the Miseans are convinced that all human society is essentially capitalistic, despite anthropological evidence to the contrary.)
I
would say that it's quite possible to conceive of a society which contains markets being free of alienation- I think that certain societies which had developed away from a gift-based model of exchange but had not developed a "bourgeois" model could be described as such- but not of "market societies" in the sense of a society organised on a fundamentally market-orientated basis, and that's the only sort of market that seems even halfway realistic in the foreseeable future.
I'm going to get sociology next year (in high school) , how closely is it linked to Marxism, because Marxism was kicked out in 1991. I made demands that we get Marxism back, but nobody was interested.
Yes and no. Yes, in that a lot of the discussion of class and production is informed by Marx, and no in that it'll be balanced out by a lot of other, opposed schools, such as Weberianism. These days it leans more towards the latter than the former. (I'm also pretty critical of the sort of Marxism that tends to float around in sociology, which is generally a positivistic, class-as-
thing sort, but that's another story.)
(Totally forgot about this one, sorry.)
There are a number of problems with labor-time as currency as I see it, one of which being that it favors those with the most capital. Suppose that the U.S. and Guatemala both produce bananas. On the American farm, the farmer, equipped to the hilt with machinery and agrichemicals, can produce 800 bananas a day in 8 hours. The Guatemalan, toiling with his hands, can produce only a mere 200. If I am understanding the idea of using labor-time, the American banana should cost 1/100 of 1hr. The Guatemalan banana, on the other hand, would cost 4/100 of 1hr.
Question: if that is the case, why would a consumer ever buy an expensive Guatemalan banana? Under a price system not tied to labor-time, the Guatemalan farmer could charge the same as his American counterpart. Yes, the Guatemalan would earn only 1/4th the American (leaving out adjustments for purchasing power that happen in less-developed countries) but the Guatemalan could still make a living, save that money and improve their capital to become more productive.
If labour-time is just a convenient mode of accounting, then it doesn't actually have to be tied to . It's already obvious that all bananas from a particular producer would be calculated as costing the same- you wouldn't charge more for bananas from a tree that needed more attention (whatever that would mean, I know sod all about bananas

)- so why would it be necessary to calculate different costs-of-distribution for different producers? Just average it across the board.
Of course, that doesn't take into account variations between different spheres of distribution- if Guatemala has only Guatemalan bananas, and the US has both Guatamala and American bananas, then a global average might not be the most reasonable approach- but that's not a cross-it-when-we-come-to-it issue.
The second problem as I see it is how the labor-time price could accurately reflect the labor-time necessary to produce something. Taking the banana example above, the bananas need to be accounted for, crated up, transported to the market, and stocked on the shelves. In a physical sense, nothing is really created out of this process, but still valuable and necessary services are being performed. So, the price of the bananas can not simply be the time it took to grow and pick them, but also all these other factors and thus the pricing problem becomes ever more confusing. On top of that, the time necessary to accumulate capital to provide these services must be factored in. Question: can you conceive of how this would be accomplished and if so, how would it work?
Those can also be represented by labour time, and factored into the final cost of the banana. Just because they aren't directly consumed doesn't mean that they aren't embodied in the banana as it sits on the shelf.
The last problem I want to mention is investment. Since the price of the good would be tied to labor-hours, how does one go about acquiring capital in order to initiate or increase production? I'm assuming that I would not be allowed to loan out my labor-time credits for interest to speculate on new products and production methods. Likewise, it seems I would not be able to purchase ownership in the company and provide capital like in the stock market.
Well, put simply, you don't. That wouldn't be communism, that would just be capitalism with an awkwardly stiff price system. A sort of libertarian USSR, strange as that is to imagine.
You have previously criticized the "production for exchange" model in favor of a "production for use" model, but now say that market mechanisms would not have no place in communist society. What is a market but voluntary exchanges? Have you changed your view on this or is there something I am missing?
To be honest, I'm really just trying to avoid being dogmatic. It's possible that pseudo-market forms involving supply-and-demand mechanisms may emerge, something like a more formalised gift economy, and I don't want to rule that out just because the word "market" is somehow tainted. Form isn't content, and if it's content that I'm interested in, then it's silly to get worked up about form.
I'm not quite sure I understand the distinction: when you get out of your chair and walk away from the computer, you still claim ownership. You still claim the right to exclude others from using that item. I would not be justified in taking the computer and keeping it for myself just because it wasn't perpetually within your reach. I similarly see no difference between that computer and the plot of land it sits on. Is there really a difference?
The difference is between a claim to possession and a claim to property. In the former case, you're only claiming a primary entitlement to possess an object, or in a broader sense to decide if others may possess it. In the latter, you're making a claim
beyond possession, a claim to intermediate between possessors and possessions; to dictate to workers in a factory how to use the machines which they possess, to demand the labour (i.e. rent) of people dwelling in a building which they possess. Claims to possession, while it can take authoritarian form in certain legal structures, can also emerge through consensus- as I said previously, this is how most peasant societies allocated land- while the latter is intrinsically authoritarian, is in its very essence the domination of one mind over another.
To make this is a bit clearer, I'd recommend the essay "From Whence Do Property Titles Arise?" by William Gillis in
Markets Not Capitalism. (Skip to page 181.) It doesn't come to all the same conclusions I might, but it deals with a lot of the same issues. (It's actually a really interesting book in general. Big part of why I've been rethinking market forms (as opposed to capitalist content) lately.)