I don't think so...
Roots
![]()
Flower
![]()
Of course, you're correct. I was thinking of a Romanesco Cauliflower. I have no idea why I confused the two

I don't think so...
Roots
![]()
Flower
![]()
If you use R^2 measure in C, it should, since then C^n=R^2n.
He has an infinite square grid which he wants to tile with identical tiles. He also wants each individual tile to admit dihedral symmetry.
In other words, if you take a single tile, it is is preserved under some horizontal reflection, some vertical reflection and under a quarter-turn rotation around the intersection of the two reflection axis.
EDIT: here is a counter-example.
Take a "cross" made up of 5 squares. Then subdivide each square in 4, to get a tile made up 20 squares. This satisfies your hypothesis, but not your conclusion.
EDIT: note that neither 1,4,5,12,13,17 (the start of the basic sequence) 1,4,5,9,12,13,16 (the start of your sequence) appears in the online encyclopedia of integer sequences.
Hmmm. Maybe we have an uncomputable sequence then? This does not follow of course, but it would explain why it is not in the encyclopedia. I'm not a professional mathematician, but I do know that tiling problems of known complexity or (un-)decidability are often used in reduction arguments establishing the complexity or (un-)decidability of other problems.
I was sort of guessing that the symmetry restrictions were so strong as to make the problem at least decidable. That guess is still on, but ...
We probably need to dive into this http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Polyomino ...
What do you mean by "uncomputable"?
For any given n, we can give an upper bound on the time it will take to know if n is in our set or not. In less precise terms, this is a "finite" problem. It is decidable. It might still be a "hard" problem.
As for the strong restrictions making the problem decidable, this is a fallacy.
Adding restrictions can make the problem harder.
For example, if we remove the symmetry conditions, then the problem is trivial. EVERY n has the property that there exist a tile with n squares than can tile the plane (take the 1 by n rectangle for example). Adding the symmetry condition makes the problem harder, because it interacts in non-trivial way with the tiling property.
Possibly the references from "Tiling the plane with copies of a single polyomino" might have something of interest.
By the way, was there an interesting motivation to this problem?
I'm not so sure. This is exactly the problem for it to be computable/decidable. For that there must be a uniform procedure that works in all cases. I do not think you can give that upper bound without such a procedure. But I'm open to suggestions. Proofs even better.![]()
I'm not so sure here either. Adding restrictions can also make the problem easier. Certainly the assumption that all tiles are squares is stronger than our current assumption - and it also makes the problem trivial.
Do you mean for solving them? Like [wiki]Gaussian elimination[/wiki]?does anybody have a sure-fire proof method of re-arranging equations? like some rules...?
*anticipates abuse from PS*
I think quackers means just algebra, rearranging the equation so it says x=<stuff> rather than y=<stuff> or similar.
An example would be handy to show the general principle of it.
Wolfram alpha will do it though
e.g.
http://www.wolframalpha.com/input/?i=solve+y=12x^2+2x+for+x