There are two classes that Hegel will come up: English and History.
Hegel is on something of a rebound, with the publication of a major English-language biography in 2000, and you will many a time find classes just on Hegel, or perhaps a dual sequence of Kant and Hegel, or German Idealism with Hegel as a strong focus, in strong analytic departments, and not just so the philosophy majors can fulfill a "history of philosophy" requirement.
Last summer i read his Outlines for the Philosophy of right and it was lacking in relevance to anything.
If you read it for an English class I'm not surprised. But any competent historian with a background in the relevant period would have heaps to say about its "relevance" as a historical work reflecting the political context, and the book itself comes up in political philosophy quite frequently.
If you really read the whole thing and gave it a good crack and came away with nothing...then you didn't try hard enough or you have no interest in the subject matter. It might be helpful to read his Phenomenology first, which is the introduction to his work, but that's another time-sink.
It was full of the typical 'rationality' that makes up what we often call the continentals.
This distinction and generalization on "continental" philosophy is silly and superficial. Read, among other things, quotes from mainstream analytics such as the following:
Find an educated layperson who has read any part of either the Nagel or Frankfurt books, as well as, say, the "Sense-Certainty" section of Hegel's Phenomenology or the "Introduction" Merleau-Ponty's Phenomenology of Perception, and then ask Ms. Heifetz's childish question: which of these philosophers are addressing "questions that are important and interesting to everyone"? The "Continental" philosophers won't win.
http://leiterreports.typepad.com/blog/2006/08/who_is_alexandr.html
Almost entirely synthetic and ethno-centric, do not bother.
Not nearly as racist as Kant...
Look, I think a lot of the philosophy that goes on in most non-analytic, "postmodern," etc. areas is a joke, and god knows what they do with Hegel in English departments (not to mention any other philosopher), but the caricatures and flat-out dismissals people make of Hegel from a sort of societal groupthink that he simply "didn't say anything" is just laughable. If there weren't strong currents in mainstream philosophy dealing with elements of Nietzsche, for example, you might have a point in saying we should just drop off all the dead German dudes, but that's not the case. Sure, maybe it's a cost-benefit consideration and it's not worth the time hacking through the jungle to figure out what Hegel said, but it doesn't mean that there's nothing in there and that you can close the lid on an entire historical and philosophical epoch as "irrelevant." Forget the gender-studies articles or whatever on Hegel and get into the real philosophy people have written about him.
Also, here's a good interview that addresses this to some degree:
Spoiler :
The question itself points to a fascinating piece of intellectual history: the reception of Hegel in the English-speaking world. First, there was the establishment of Analytic philosophy by Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore in the beginning of the 20th century, which was itself always billed by both of them as an attack on "Hegelianism" in particular and "idealism" in general. Part of the force of that attack had to do particularly with Russell's own, rather stark modernism. He and that whole Edwardian generation were rebelling against the overdecorated Victorian house and against what they saw as irrational, suffocating Victorian morals—in short, against the whole panoply of overstuffed, overdecorated, pompous Victorian "earnestness" (think of Oscar Wilde's witty play on Victorian stuffiness) and the puffed-up excess that seemed to go with it. Against all of that, men cut their hair, shaved their mutton chops, and started wearing modern suits. Modern, rigorous houses were built, modernism in poetry became a movement unto itself, and so forth.
All these things signified a cultural change of no small magnitude. In philosophy this was touted as a defense of reason, a truly "scientific" approach to things, a mathematization of theory, a paring down to the arguments pro and con for a position, and the like. For Russell, the opposite of all that was the overly inflated, pretentious "Hegelianism" of his day. "Hegelianism" seemed like the perfect philosophical embodiment of everything that the "modernists" (in art, architecture, painting, poetry, and philosophy) were against. Thus, one of the great achievements of Anglophone philosophy—the invention of Analytic philosophy, its techniques of argument, its professionalized style, its extreme seriousness about itself—was achieved by, as it were, "killing off" Hegel. There is something almost Oedipal in the reaction of Anglophone philosophers to Hegel: He just had to be dead. Analytic philosophy could only be created by "killing" the Hegelians (Russell's and Moore's teachers); if Hegel were to return, the whole Analytic show, it was felt, would be doomed.
The other set of events had to do with the demonization of Germany in World War I and the German moral catastrophe that led to World War II. In both cases, for rather spurious and scandalous reasons, Hegel became identified with the kind of "Teutonism" that gave all things German a bad name. The Nazis never liked Hegel, and he was always considered by the party hacks to have too much "Jewish" influence in his thought to be really German. (Of course, there were also opportunistic philosophers in Germany trying to make Hegel, just as they tried to make all kinds of other German philosophers, into heroes of Hitler's state.) Nonetheless, in English-speaking countries, "Hegel" (already the bane of Analytic philosophers poised for their postwar takeover of philosophy departments) became the evil German Hegel. He thus became not only stuffy and pretentious, to be jettisoned in favor of the cool, sparse, argumentative rigor of Analytic philosophy; he became evil.
Those two events—the attack on Hegel that led to the establishment of Analytic philosophy and the false identification of Hegel with German militarism and Nazi terror—made Hegel persona non grata in the Anglophone world until, really, only a few years ago. Only now has Hegel begun to be taken seriously enough that anybody would think of writing such a biography.
Of course Hegel never left continental European philosophy, where people were not taken in by the idea that he was a gasbag who couldn't "argue" or was really in his heart a proto-Nazi. Hegel simply never got burdened with those misreadings on the continent, where he stayed alive while he lived at best an underground existence in Britain, the United States, and Australia.
All these things signified a cultural change of no small magnitude. In philosophy this was touted as a defense of reason, a truly "scientific" approach to things, a mathematization of theory, a paring down to the arguments pro and con for a position, and the like. For Russell, the opposite of all that was the overly inflated, pretentious "Hegelianism" of his day. "Hegelianism" seemed like the perfect philosophical embodiment of everything that the "modernists" (in art, architecture, painting, poetry, and philosophy) were against. Thus, one of the great achievements of Anglophone philosophy—the invention of Analytic philosophy, its techniques of argument, its professionalized style, its extreme seriousness about itself—was achieved by, as it were, "killing off" Hegel. There is something almost Oedipal in the reaction of Anglophone philosophers to Hegel: He just had to be dead. Analytic philosophy could only be created by "killing" the Hegelians (Russell's and Moore's teachers); if Hegel were to return, the whole Analytic show, it was felt, would be doomed.
The other set of events had to do with the demonization of Germany in World War I and the German moral catastrophe that led to World War II. In both cases, for rather spurious and scandalous reasons, Hegel became identified with the kind of "Teutonism" that gave all things German a bad name. The Nazis never liked Hegel, and he was always considered by the party hacks to have too much "Jewish" influence in his thought to be really German. (Of course, there were also opportunistic philosophers in Germany trying to make Hegel, just as they tried to make all kinds of other German philosophers, into heroes of Hitler's state.) Nonetheless, in English-speaking countries, "Hegel" (already the bane of Analytic philosophers poised for their postwar takeover of philosophy departments) became the evil German Hegel. He thus became not only stuffy and pretentious, to be jettisoned in favor of the cool, sparse, argumentative rigor of Analytic philosophy; he became evil.
Those two events—the attack on Hegel that led to the establishment of Analytic philosophy and the false identification of Hegel with German militarism and Nazi terror—made Hegel persona non grata in the Anglophone world until, really, only a few years ago. Only now has Hegel begun to be taken seriously enough that anybody would think of writing such a biography.
Of course Hegel never left continental European philosophy, where people were not taken in by the idea that he was a gasbag who couldn't "argue" or was really in his heart a proto-Nazi. Hegel simply never got burdened with those misreadings on the continent, where he stayed alive while he lived at best an underground existence in Britain, the United States, and Australia.
http://www.postelservice.com/archives/000008.html
(Sorry to hijack the thread.)