Also, Plotinus -- you've may have answered this already, so I apologize if so -- what can you tell me about the historical doctrine of limbo? The impression I got is that it came about post-Augustine. Were there pre-Augustinian conceptions of limbo? Do you know who is credited with the first real formulation of the idea of Limbo?
I don't know much about this, but as I understand it, limbo was a medieval development of Augustine's belief that some people (notably unbaptised babies) are justly consigned to hell but only the very lightest version of hell. So they will suffer, but not so much. Peter Abelard, thinking this a bit harsh, amended it so that unbaptised babies don't suffer at all, although they don't enjoy much happiness either - they're just somewhere in between. So Abelard is often credited with being the first theologian to speak of limbo proper. The idea was later extended to include other categories of people, such as virtuous pagans, as in Dante.
Plot, I seem to recall that you mentioned that theologians/anthropologists/whomever distinguish between "religion" and "magic". What is the difference? I had thought there was no agreed-upon definition of "magic" in this context (colloquially, it means "invoking forces I, the speaker, don't believe in" and is pretty much always used pejoratively).
As I understand it, magic - speaking anthropologically - is when a person tries to influence events at a higher level by manipulating objects at a lower level. For example, in sympathetic magic you try to control a person by fiddling about with their nail clippings or a doll that looks like them, or whatever it may be. In the Neoplatonic magical tradition (deriving from Iamblichus), there is a hierarchy in nature from the highest beings to the lowest beings, with intermediate ones in the middle. The ones in the middle share some of the nature of the ones at the top and also some of the nature of the ones at the bottom, so they are complex. The ones at the top and the ones at the bottom, despite being at opposite ends of the hierarchy, therefore have an affinity in that they are more simple. So you can affect what happens at the top by acting upon the ones at the bottom. Hence the use of base or simple substances to try to control the divine realm.
So magic is in effect a sort of technology, at least in theory - it's done by
doing things which you hope will affect other things, via a natural mechanism.
In religion, by contrast, there's no manipulation of elements - you achieve things by asking a god to do it for you. That's not to say that a religion can't contain magical elements, and of course it's a traditional criticism of Catholicism that many of its rituals and practices are effectively magical rather than devotional. But there's still a big conceptual difference between the two.
Did Augustine believe that Mary was sinful? If she was born free of Original Sin, does that mean or imply that she did not sin?
Augustine did not believe that Mary was born free of original sin. The belief that she was is the doctrine of the immaculate conception, which was medieval. However, Augustine seems to have thought that divine grace permitted her to lead a life in which she never did perform any sin. (When Pelagius gave examples of people he thought had lived sinful lives, Mary was the only one that Augustine was prepared to accept.)
Which historical Christian groups believed in salvation by good works? I've only ever heard of people rejecting it in favor of salvation by faith alone.
Well, the Pelagians! One might add to that the communities associated with Matthew's Gospel and the letter of James - perhaps. But "salvation by works" is one of those things that no-one wants to say they believe - it's always a stick used to beat others with. Even Pelagius talked about faith and grace.
I think a large number of Arminians believe in total depravity but reject unconditional election. Arminians, as I understand it, don't believe in works based salvation, so it would not make sense for them to believe that God would rank people based on their actions.
Is that necessarily so? There's a difference between saying that God chooses whom to save on the basis of what they have done, and saying that it's what people do that saves them. It seems to me possible for someone to believe that our actions do not save us, but that God nevertheless chooses whom to save on the basis of actions. For example, perhaps God chooses to save all those people (and only those people) who have worn a green pair of shoes. Now it wouldn't follow from that that wearing a green pair of shoes is
what saves you; it's simply
what defines the group of people whom God saves. In fact, there's an influential interpretation of Paul that argues that it is this view, rather than the view that your actions are what save you, that he opposes when he talks about faith and works. And when Paul says that those who have faith will be saved, he (similarly) isn't saying that it's faith that saves you - rather, it's simply that those who have faith are those who will be saved, not that there's a (direct) causal connection between these properties.
I don't think that is a modern phenomenon at all. People often ask Jesus what they must do to be saved in the gospels.
Mark 10:26
The disciples were even more amazed, and said to each other, Who then can be saved?
Luke 7:50
Jesus said to the woman, Your faith has saved you; go in peace.
Luke 13:23
Someone asked him, Lord, are only a few people going to be saved?
Luke 18:26
Those who heard this asked, Who then can be saved?
Luke 23:35
The people stood watching, and the rulers even sneered at him. They said, He saved others; let him save himself if he is Gods Messiah, the Chosen One.
Here is a verse from each gospel where Jesus talks about how to be saved, or not saved.
Mark 16:16
Whoever believes and is baptized will be saved, but whoever does not believe will be condemned.
Luke 8:12
Those along the path are the ones who hear, and then the devil comes and takes away the word from their hearts, so that they may not believe and be saved.
Matthew 24:10-13
At that time many will turn away from the faith and will betray and hate each other, and many false prophets will appear and deceive many people. Because of the increase of wickedness, the love of most will grow cold, but the one who stands firm to the end will be saved.
John 10:9
I am the gate; whoever enters through me will be saved. They will come in and go out, and find pasture.
Those are good points (although if we're talking about the historical Jesus rather than the concerns of the authors of the Gospels, I would dispute the Mark verse as being barely canonical, let alone authentic, and the John one as being probably inauthentic). But I still don't think it's a defining issue in the New Testament, the way that it is in the Reformed tradition. Of the five points of Calvinism, four are about salvation. Compare that to the Nicene Creed, which doesn't mention salvation at all, but instead has some brief statements at the end about the forgiveness of sins and the resurrection of the dead. Now of course a Calvinist would say that those are references to salvation. My point was simply that that's an interpretation; the word "salvation" doesn't occur in that text or in many similar ones, and to reduce complex and varied ideas such as forgiveness, resurrection, eternal life, the kingdom of God, and all the rest to the simple and undifferentiated heading of "salvation" is to lose something.
Ephesians 2:8
For it is by grace you have been saved, through faith
Romans 8:24
For in this hope we were saved. But hope that is seen is no hope at all.
Paul also does reference salvation as a future event as well, but that is because there are three phases to salvation that Paul talks about, Justification (past), sanctification (current) and glorification (future).
Paul didn't write Ephesians. The Romans verse is interesting - it's actually in the aorist tense, which is temporally vague, being past or present. You are right, though, it is not future (or at least not explicitly so). Perhaps I would have been more accurate if I'd said that Paul never refers to salvation as something that is past. I'd say that your distinction between the three phases that Paul talks about sounds about right, but what's the evidence that Paul thought that these were three phases
of salvation?
I think one can look at Jesus's teaching on the Kingdom and see that it is related to salvation.
In John 3:1-15 Jesus seems to use "The Kingdom of God", "Eternal Life" and "Heaven" interchangeably. He stats that to receive these things you must be born again. Salvation, as I understand it, is being saved from hell and inheriting eternal life.
In Matthew 24:12-13 (quoted above) Jesus says that "the one who stands firm to the end will be saved" is the "gospel of the Kingdom". I know there are other passages that make the Kingdom of God seems like something else, I think it best understood as God's "rule" or "reign". So if it is in reference to entering someones heart, that would be establishing God's rule in your heart, if it is on reference to earth, it would be establishing God's rule on earth. It could also obviously be used in reference to heaven, as that is where God's rule is established. So when Jesus talks about inheriting the Kingdom of God, I think he is talking about salvation.
The meaning of the kingdom of God passages is of course dreadfully disputed, because there are so many categories of them that no single meaning can make sense of them all. Sometimes the kingdom is external to people, sometimes it is internal; sometimes it is coming in the future, sometimes it is already here; sometimes it is something one enters, sometimes it is something inside you. I think you are right to say that the concept overlaps with that of salvation, at least some of the time. But I wouldn't say it's the same thing. I think the John passage you cite reflects later Christian reflection on these different concepts and shows people trying to assimilate them to each other; I don't think this reflects Jesus' own use or understanding of the term "kingdom of God".
I don't understand what you mean by that doctrine (I've never heard of it), but that's not what I mean (And again, I may not be right, that's just what I think it means based of limited knowledge.)
Messalianism was a movement in fifth-century Syria. The Messalians (apparently) believed (among other things) that the presence of the Holy Spirit could be consciously felt, and that this was a litmus test of whether the Spirit was in you or not. If you could feel him, he was there, and if you couldn't, he wasn't. It's certainly rather an obscure heresy but quite an interesting one. (They were also accused of believing that going to the toilet was a way of expelling sin from your body.)
What I meant was, if someone continually, repetitively sins, he knows he is sinning, he does not repent, and he feels no guilt, the believer in Eternal Security would say "Well, as long as he was saved once" while the Perseverance of the Saints believer would say he was never saved since if he was, he would feel guilt.
Right, I understand.
Well, I don't think anyone I know would accept Total Depravity as you explained it (Maybe a few) but I don't think that that is necessarily the correct interpretation (I'll ask you to clarify in a second). Most people I know hold to some form of Perseverance of the Saints. The rest of Calvinism... until a couple of years ago most people I knew did not believe it, but a lot of them (Not all, but many) changed their views (There are still numerous things about both sides that bother me, so I still have no view.)
I think this is incorrect. I think (Correct me if I'm wrong) that Total Depravity merely means that man is unable to choose God on his own, or do good on its own. This is different that everything is sinful, which makes no sense. That said, saying that our HEART is always sinful might make sense.
For instance, if I help an old lady, is that Sin? Even if my reasons are selfish, no its not, the fact that I am selfish in my heart is the Sin, but my action was not a sin. Note that it was not good either, for doing good is only possible if it was done for Christ.
Sinfulness is a matter of intent, surely. If you do something that in itself is good (such as helping someone), but you do it from sinful motives (as the doctrine of total depravity states), then surely your action is sinful - because whether it is sinful or not is determined entirely by the intent - isn't it? Of course it's not sinful
in itself, considered as the kind of act that it is, but you are performing it with a sinful intent.
That's how I understand it, anyway. But then I don't know much about Reformed theology (as already mentioned), so perhaps that's not how it's usually seen. Certainly if you can make a strong distinction between the sinfulness (or otherwise) of the intent and the sinfulness (or otherwise) of the act then one could say that not all acts are sinful, even though all intents are.
I see zero reason to assume John the Baptist's message was incorrect.
No doubt, but I don't see what that has to do with what I said - I didn't comment on the rightness or wrongness of John the Baptist's message.
If Jesus did not tell a given sinner to repent, that does not mean that was needed for Salvation. God loved the sinner, yet hated their sin. And Christ said "Today Salvation has come to this House" to Zacchaeus only AFTER he repented.
That's true, but I'm not sure it makes much difference to what I said; the point is that Jesus isn't represented as telling Zacchaeus, or most people, to repent. The impression given by the Synoptic Gospels is that, if repentance was part of Jesus' message, it was a pretty minor part.
1. If you know something is Sin and still do it, but do not deliberately choose it with the mindset that it is Sin (After Baptism) are you damned? For instance, say someone is tempted by a woman when he is already married, she seduces him, and they have sex. The man already knows the appropriate Biblical condemnations against adultery and knows it is sinful, but he does not have this in his mind when he does it. Is he damned?
I think pretty much all moral theologians would hold that if you commit a sin that you know is a sin, then that counts as a sinful act whether or not you're consciously thinking of its sinfulness at the time. Why wouldn't it?
What you describe is actually very similar to Aristotle's explanation of
acrasia or weakness of will, which is where somebody does something that they know to be wrong (or against their own interests). This was a problem to Greek philosophers as it was a basic tenet of theirs that everyone does what they think is best, and that if someone does something wrong it is because they mistakenly believe it's the best thing to do. And yet common experience tells us that people do things like eating cream cakes whilst saying "I know I shouldn't eat this!" Aristotle explained it by saying that, although the person knows that they shouldn't do it, their desire to do it temporarily overpowers their knowledge, so at that moment, they actually don't know it's wrong (at least not consciously), no matter what they say. However, the person is still responsible for their act, to the extent that they had the power to resist their desire.
2. If Pelagius says that something is only sin if you know it is Sin, or if you think it is and do it even if it is not normally a Sin, isn't Pelagianism basically reletivistic, basically you can do what you like and reach Salvation as long as you can convince yourself there is nothing wrong with it?
The view you ascribe to Pelagius isn't exclusive to him - it's what most Christian moralists would say. As I said, it is usual to say that the
sinfulness of an act is determined by the
intent with which it is performed. That does not lead to relativism because it can still be the case that there are absolute and universal moral laws. If you intend to break the moral law, then you act sinfully; if you intend to keep the moral law, then you do not act sinfully. That's distinct from whether you
actually do break or keep the moral law. So there can remain clear and universal standards for whether a person is behaving sinfully and also for whether their actions are right or wrong. Relativism would involve denying both of these.
Now there are traditions within Catholic moral theology that allow for a certain amount of "excusing". The Jesuits taught, in the past, an ethical theory known as probabilism, which basically states that, when you're unsure what the right thing to do is, you are not acting sinfully provided you make a choice that has a good chance of being the right thing to do. This is so even if an alternative choice seems to have a
better chance of being the right thing to do. Critics of the Jesuits (of whom there were many) said that this effectively meant that people could do anything they wanted provided they could think up some feeble justification for it, and indeed it seems that perhaps some Jesuit thinkers did verge on that. In practice, of course, the theory was intended to provide a realistic moral standard that didn't demand the impossible of people - in other words, it was precisely the opposite of Pelagianism.
But neither Pelagius nor a Jesuit probabilist nor any mainstream Christian moralist would think that you can do what you like as long as you convince yourself that there's nothing wrong with it, because how could one do that? Could you really, say, murder someone and convince yourself that it's the right thing to do? Well, perhaps - in fact the
Memoirs and confessions of a justified sinner is all about someone who does precisely that, and uses Calvinist theology to rationalise it, to boot. But someone like that is reasoning in such a warped way that, even if they are genuinely ignorant that their act is sinful, that itself is culpable ignorance. In other words, to get oneself into a state like that would itself be an egregious sin.
3. The key to Pelagian theology is "After Baptism" if you Sin, you lose your Salvation. What if you are baptized at infancy before you even believed, then you sin before actually placing your trust in Christ. Would Pelagius say you are damned or not?
I don't know. Pelagianism generally didn't see much point in infant baptism, because Pelagians didn't believe that there was any inherited guilt that needed removing. Pelagius himself approved of infant baptism, not to remove sin but to allow entrance into the kingdom. It seems to me that in the case you describe, there wouldn't be much hope for the person in question. But I don't think that Pelagius or any other ancient Christian would have conceived of this case, because they didn't think in terms of salvation/damnation being about "placing your trust in Christ", at least not in a way that distinguished that from baptism or church membership.
When I say that, I don't mean to imply that they didn't think trust in Christ was important or that they couldn't understand the concept of someone trusting in Christ without being baptised, or vice versa. I mean that this just wasn't the way that they typically thought.
4. You spoke earlier about the people who deliberately saved Salvation until near death. Why would any Pelagian NOT do this?
Quite - I don't think it would make sense not to, for a Pelagian.
Also, why would Christ set up a system of Salvation that essentially rewards putting off his command (Baptism) until the last minute, and purposely making it harder for those who follow his command immediately.
It's not about "setting up a system of salvation" - salvation works the way it works! The early Christians took baptism extremely seriously. They thought it should not be done frivolously or quickly, because it was so important. Look at
Tertullian's treatise on this subject, particularly ch. 18. He points out that you don't get married at the drop of a hat but wait until the right time. It's the same with baptism. Now he's not arguing for delaying baptism until the last minute, but that practice arose from the same concerns. Of course, there would be a risk in doing that, because what if you died before you'd got around to being baptised? The early Christians certainly thought baptism necessary for salvation. I think the general attitude was that God would want people to get baptised at the appropriate time, and that delaying it excessively was a bit cheeky. So Gregory of Nazianzus, as a young man, was caught in a storm at sea and prayed that if he was delivered, he would get baptised - having presumably intended to hold off for as long as possible. That pretty much sums up the attitude.